Semantics is the science of meaning in language.

Semantics is the study of meaning in language. Introduced into English in the late 19th century, the term has since competed with such other terms as “semasiology”, “semology” and “semics” to identify a possible science of meaning. It is now the most widely used label for such a science, despite the popular pejorative sense which has developed in everyday speech (as in “That’s just semantics”, i.e. quibbling unnecessarily over word meanings, or deliberately using language to mislead or confuse). Semantics is one of the main components, or levels, of linguistic analysis (cf p. 19). Given that the communication of meaning is the central function of language, we might thus expect semantics to be the most well-developed branch of linguistics. But semantic studies have lagged behind most other aspects of linguistic investigation, partly because of linguists’ preoccupation with phonetics, phonology and grammar, and partly because of fundamental difficulties in subjecting the notion of “meaning” to successful analysis. In the 1960s and 1970s, however, the subject attracted increasing attention in linguistics, so that there are now several introductory texts available) and several advanced reviews of the field2. There is as yet no orthodoxy in semantics, but certain common themes have emerged in this literature which can help to distinguish linguistic semantics from other, more well-established approaches to the study of meaning-in particular, those which take their rise from philosophy and psychology.

Keywords

  • Language Acquisition
  • Semantic Feature
  • Semantic Structure
  • Semantic Function
  • Semantic Field

These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.

Buying options

Chapter

EUR   29.95

Price includes VAT (Singapore)
  • DOI: 10.1007/978-3-7091-4001-7_5
  • Chapter length: 61 pages
  • Instant PDF download
  • Readable on all devices
  • Own it forever
  • Exclusive offer for individuals only
  • Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout
Buy Chapter

eBookEUR   74.89Price includes VAT (Singapore)

  • ISBN: 978-3-7091-4001-7
  • Instant PDF download
  • Readable on all devices
  • Own it forever
  • Exclusive offer for individuals only
  • Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout
Buy eBook

Softcover BookEUR   89.99Price excludes VAT (Singapore)

  • ISBN: 978-3-7091-4003-1
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Exclusive offer for individuals only
  • Free shipping worldwide
    Shipping restrictions may apply, check to see if you are impacted.
  • Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout
Buy Softcover Book

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. For example, Palmer (1976), Leech (1974), Lyons (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  2. For example, Fillmore and Langendoen (1971), Steinberg and Jakobovitz (1971).

    Google Scholar 

  3. For example, the work of Charles Peirce, Rudolf Carnap and Alfred Tarski; see the review in Lyons ( 1977: Ch. 4).

    Google Scholar 

  4. See Ullmann (1973), Stankiewicz (1964).

    Google Scholar 

  5. For behaviourist semantics, see Osgood (1953), Bloomfield (1933) and the review in Lyons (1977: Ch. 5); for mentalistic semantics, see de Saussure (1916), Ogden and Richards (1923) and the review in Lyons (1977: Ch. 4 ).

    Google Scholar 

  6. For example, the work of Ayer (1936), Strawson (1971), Wittgenstein (1953).

    Google Scholar 

  7. For example, Rodgon, Jankowski and Alenskas (1977); see further, p. 175.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See Collinson (1981) for a historical review.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Other broad conceptions, which emphasize the relationship between linguistic and philosophical/logical theories of meaning, are illustrated by Fillmore and Langendoen (1971), Leech (1974) and Keenan (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Note, in this respect, that linguists see “meaning” both as a datum and as a criterion of analysis. Linguists study meaning, and also use meaning to study other aspects of language, through such notions as “contrastivity” and “distinctiveness”.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. Piaget (1926), Donaldson (1978).

    Google Scholar 

  12. For a development of this view, see for example Bloom (1973: 20 ff.), Schlesinger (1977, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  13. The point of the phrase “linguistic units” is to draw attention to the range oflinguistic structures which communicate meaning. It contrasts with a traditional view that all that is involved in semantics is the relationship between “words”, or “names”, and “things”.

    Google Scholar 

  14. For example, Lyons ( 1968: Ch. 2), Palmer (1971: Ch. 2 ).

    Google Scholar 

  15. The introduction of encyclopaedic information, pictorial aids, etc. into some dictionaries, as an aid to immediacy of understanding, should be seen as a separate development, in principle distinguishable from the need to provide linguistic definitions throughout.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Dictionary examples throughout this chapter will be taken from the Longman Dictionary of Contemporary English (Procter, 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  17. See for example the discussion in Bloom (1973).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Most vocabulary counts are based on written language samples, whether for child (e.g. Edwards and Gibbon 1973) or adult (e.g. Thorndike and Lorge 1944).

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Lyons (1977: 250–261), Robins (1971: 66–69). For the original German ideas, see Trier (1934); for developments by American anthropologists, see the papers in Part 4 (“Cultural focus and semantic field”) of Hymes (1964: 167–214). Much of the cogency of the original proposals lay in the illuminating comparisons of different languages or language states—demonstrating, for example, that lexemes were not totally equivalent in their domain of application between languages (see the discussion of the difficulties of translating the cat sat on the mat into French in Lyons (1977:237–2381), or that there were gaps in the lexical expression of one language compared with another (well-discussed examples such as the range of words for“snow” in Eskimo, compared with English),In this chapter, the illustration will be wholly from English, and this comparative dimension will be only indirectly referred to. It should also be noted that a different sense of“semantic field” is found in the neuropsychological use of the term by Luria, where it refers to the sound and meaning associations of a word with other words, as determined by the physiological measurement of orienting reactions. Lesser (1978) also prefers a more general sense for this term, using “semantic category” in its place.

    Google Scholar 

  20. It should perhaps be pointed out that only a small proportion of the data is relevant to this question, as the following statistics show: of all the words used by the clinicians, 55% were grammatical, 9% were social or stereotyped (in the sense of Crystal, Fletcher and Garman 1976), and 2% were proper names; which leaves only 34% for semantically “full” lexemes.

    Google Scholar 

  21. A “theme”, in this sense, does not constitute a semantic field: it is a non-linguistically motivated notion, which cuts across the notion of semantic field, and may use lexemes from several of them. For example, the theme “What can you see at the zoo?” could be correctly answered by lion, tiger,etc. (field: ANIMALS), cages, cafe (field: BUILDINGS), boys, girls,etc. (field: PEOPLE), and so on. Examples of other themes include the story-lines of novels, plays, fairy-stories, etc. To determine when P can determine a theme from a list (e.g. queen… mirror… cottage… seven beds… dwarfs…) is an interesting exercise, but it is not one directly involving semantic structure.

    Google Scholar 

  22. In logic, contradictory terms are those where p and q cannot both be true or both false, e.g. if X is male, X cannot be female, and vice versa: one cannot be both male/female or neither male/female. Contrary terms are those where p and q cannot both be true, but both may be false, e.g. if X is hot,X cannot be cold,but X may be neither hot nor cold, e.g. lukewarm.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Experimental studies aiming to show differential ability, both in production and comprehension, have been frequent in child language acquisition, for certain areas of the vocabulary: see, for example, Eilers, 011er and Ellington (1974).

    Google Scholar 

  24. See Firth (1951: 194 ff.), Halliday (1966), Robins (1971: 63–66). Sometimes the term is used for all co-occurrences between lexemes—including the house/wall type nor is there as clear a boundary between these two types as the above examples might suggest—cf. Palmer (1976: 96).

    Google Scholar 

  25. See, for example, the methods used by Sinclair(1966), on the basis of the approach summarised in Halliday (1966).

    Google Scholar 

  26. See Lounsbury (1956), Katz and Fodor (1963).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Cf. the baby-talk prosody of parents: see the paper by Garnica, and other references in Snow and Ferguson (1977); also above, p. 93. On the social function of accents, see Trudgill (1974), Giles and Powesland (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. Empson (1930), Firth (1951: 193–194), Leech (1969: Ch. 6 ).

    Google Scholar 

  29. In some accounts of linguistic analysis, the patterns discussed below would in fact be handled under the heading of grammar, and not in this Chapter at all. The boundary between syntax and semantics is always somewhat arbitrarily decided.

    Google Scholar 

  30. See for example Fillmore (1968), Chafe (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  31. These are based on a comparison of the functions recognised in Brown (1973), Bowerman (1973), Wells (1974), Bloom, Lightbown and Hood (1975), and Bloom and Lahey (1978), with the further references therein.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Cf. the grammatical classification of Quirk, et al ( 1972: Ch. 3).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Note the close cognitive relationship between space and time in early development, as argued by H. Clark (1973).

    Google Scholar 

  34. See Nelson (1973, 1974), Clark (1973), Bloom (1973), Anglin (1977), Bloom and Lahey ( 1978: Ch. 4). Summaries may be found in Clark and Clark (1977: Ch. 13) and Fletcher and Garman (1979: Chs. 8, 9 ).

    Google Scholar 

  35. Some lexemes may of course be used in both a static and a dynamic interpretation. Cf. Quirk et al. (1972: Ch. 3), though their purpose is to identify the grammatical constraints operating upon verbs, and not to provide a semantic classification in its own right.

    Google Scholar 

  36. See Nelson (1973), Chambers and Tavuchis (1976), Cruse (1977), Andersen (1978), Clark (1979), Rescorla (1981), and, for an early review, Nice (1915).

    Google Scholar 

  37. See Berlin, Breedlove and Raven (1973); also Anglin (1977), Clark (1979).

    Google Scholar 

  38. One such framework is illustrated in Crystal (1982).

    Google Scholar 

  39. See Bloom and Lahey (1978: 116ff.), Clark (1974), Anglin (1977), Reich (1976).

    Google Scholar 

  40. See the discussion in Thomson and Chapman (1977), Fremgen and Fay (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  41. See E. Clark (1973), Nelson (1974).

    Google Scholar 

  42. See Bloom, Lightbown and Hood (1975), Bloom and Lahey ( 1978: 134 ).

    Google Scholar 

  43. The acquisition of definitional form and function is discussed by Litowitz (1977) and Wehren, De Lisi and Arnold (1981).

    Google Scholar 

  44. For the former, see Eilers, Oiler and Ellington (1974), Bartlett (1976); for the latter, Haviland and Clark (1974), Chambers and Tavuchis (1976).

    Google Scholar 

  45. See Rosch (1973), Rosch and Lloyd (1978), Anglin (1977). For the relevant cognitive psychological support, see, e.g. Posner (1973), Reed (1972).

    Google Scholar 

  46. See, for example, Berndt and Caramazza (1978), Crystal and Davy (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  47. See Winner (1979), Gardner ( 1974 ), Gardner, Kircher, Winner and Perkins (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  48. See Brown (1973), Bowerman (1973), Wells (1974), Bloom, Lightbown and Hood (1975), Greenfield and Smith (1976), Bloom and Lahey (1978: Ch. 4), Macrae (1979). For a critique, see Howe (1976) and the further discussion in Journal of Child Language, 8. 2. (1981).

    Google Scholar 

  49. See Bloom, Lahey, Hood, Lifter and Fiess (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  50. See Clark (1971), Hatch (1971), French and Brown (1977), Coker (1978).

    Google Scholar 

  51. For an example of the interaction between grammatical and semantic variables in an area of considerable clinical importance, we may refer to the development of question forms, p. 103.

    Google Scholar 

  52. See Goldin-Meadow, Seligman and Gelman (1976), Benedict (1979). Average number of (different) lexemes in production are:10 by 1:2,50 by 1:6,100 by 1:7,200 by 1:9,and 300 by 2:0. However, in the early period, the ratio of number of lexemes comprehended to number produced is about 5:1, with often a gap of several months between comprehension and production. On average, comprehension development moves at the rate of just over 20 new lexemes per month; production just under 10 per month. The distinction becomes much less important after age 2.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Cf.Aram and Nation (1975), and fn. 16 in Ch. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  54. It is obviously important for T to know the target item, before a decision about relatedness can be made; similarly, a lot depends on the unambiguity of the stimulus.

    Google Scholar 

  55. These strictly intra-linguistic observations of course constitute only a part of a theory of lexical retrieval—but they are an important part. For broader, psycholinguistic accounts, within which structural semantic notions might be incorporated, see Forster (1978), Morton (1979).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

  1. Department of Linguistic Science, University of Reading, Great Britain

    Prof. Dr. David Crystal

Authors

  1. Prof. Dr. David Crystal

    View author publications

    You can also search for this author in PubMed Google Scholar

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

© 1981 Springer-Verlag Wien

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Crystal, D. (1981). Semantics. In: Clinical Linguistics. Disorders of Human Communication, vol 3. Springer, Vienna. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-7091-4001-7_5

What is a semantic in language?

What Does Semantics Mean? Semantics is the study of the meaning of words and sentences. It uses the relations of linguistic forms to non-linguistic concepts and mental representations to explain how sentences are understood by native speakers.

Is semantics the same as meaning?

Semantics is the study of meaning in language. It can be applied to entire texts or to single words. For example, "destination" and "last stop" technically mean the same thing, but students of semantics analyze their subtle shades of meaning.

Is semantics part of language?

Semantics is the study of meaning in language. The semantic component is the meaning conveyed by words, phrases and sentences. Semantics includes a person's vocabulary or lexicon.

What is semantics according to Chomsky?

Semantics for Chomsky must be part of I-language: the part that provides useful information from the Language Faculty to the Conceptual-Intentional system. There are many traditions in semantics, and many current research programs in sematics are embedded in firmly anti-Chomskyan views of language in general.